Why is a symmetric relation defined: $forall xforall y( xRyimplies yRx)$ and not $forall xforall y (xRyiff yRx)$? Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern)How to prove relation is asymmetric if it is both anti-symmetric and irreflexiveIs an Anti-Symmetric Relation also Reflexive?Graph, Relation $xRy Leftrightarrow$ There is a path between $x$ and $y$ - symmetryDefine symmetric relation R on set SProve that if $R$ is a symmetric, transitive relation on $A$ and the domain of $R$ is $A$, then $R$ is reflexive on $A$.If R is symmetric, must $S=forall xin X exists yin Y (xRy) $ be symmetric?Given set A, is the relation A x A always anti symmetric?Definition of symmetric relationName for relation property: If $xRy$ and $xRz$ and $x not =y$, then $yRz$.Can a relation be transitive when it is symmetric but not reflexive?
Circular Orbits Around a Reissner-Nordstrom Black Hole
Why weren't discrete x86 CPUs ever used in game hardware?
Is it dangerous to install hacking tools on my private linux machine?
Do I really need to have a message in a novel to appeal to readers?
What are the geometrical meaning higher Chern forms and classes?
Understanding p-Values using an example
Find Maximum of any discrete function (not necessarily a PDF)
Why does it sometimes sound good to play a grace note as a lead in to a note in a melody?
What does this say in Elvish?
What does it mean that physics no longer uses mechanical models to describe phenomena?
How do living politicians protect their readily obtainable signatures from misuse?
I can't update due to The repository 'http://download.opensuse.org/repositories/home:/strycore/xUbuntu_16.04 ./ Release' is not signed
Does the Mueller report show a conspiracy between Russia and the Trump Campaign?
Manga where all the characters were human/animal hybrids
Did Mueller's report provide an evidentiary basis for the claim of Russian govt election interference via social media?
Central Vacuuming: Is it worth it, and how does it compare to normal vacuuming?
Why do early math courses focus on the cross sections of a cone and not on other 3D objects?
A term for a woman complaining about things/begging in a cute/childish way
Tannaka duality for semisimple groups
Should a wizard buy fine inks every time he want to copy spells into his spellbook?
Fit (vertically portrayed) image with the caption displayed below
Strange behavior of Object.defineProperty() in JavaScript
What does Turing mean by this statement?
How many morphisms from 1 to 1+1 can there be?
Why is a symmetric relation defined: $forall xforall y( xRyimplies yRx)$ and not $forall xforall y (xRyiff yRx)$?
Announcing the arrival of Valued Associate #679: Cesar Manara
Planned maintenance scheduled April 23, 2019 at 23:30 UTC (7:30pm US/Eastern)How to prove relation is asymmetric if it is both anti-symmetric and irreflexiveIs an Anti-Symmetric Relation also Reflexive?Graph, Relation $xRy Leftrightarrow$ There is a path between $x$ and $y$ - symmetryDefine symmetric relation R on set SProve that if $R$ is a symmetric, transitive relation on $A$ and the domain of $R$ is $A$, then $R$ is reflexive on $A$.If R is symmetric, must $S=forall xin X exists yin Y (xRy) $ be symmetric?Given set A, is the relation A x A always anti symmetric?Definition of symmetric relationName for relation property: If $xRy$ and $xRz$ and $x not =y$, then $yRz$.Can a relation be transitive when it is symmetric but not reflexive?
$begingroup$
Why is a symmetric relation defined by $forallxforally(xRy implies yRx)$ and not $forallxforally(xRy iff yRx)$?
(I have only found a couple of sources that defines it with a biconditional)
For example, according to Wolfram:
A relation $R$ on a set $S$ is symmetric provided that for every $x$ and $y$ in $S$ we have $xRy iff yRx$.
But the majority of books defines it the other way.
And I think I agree with the second definition.
Because if we use the first definition with "$implies$", we know the truth table of the implication in particular $P implies Q$ is true when $P$ is false and $Q$ is true. That means in the context of symmetric relation that $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And the example $A = 1,2,3,4$ with relation $R = (2,1),(3,1),(4,1)$ satisfies the definition because $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And for me it's weird that this case is considered symmetric.
Or maybe I have a profound confusion with the concept.
I would like that you guys help me clarify. *Sorry for my grammar I'm not a native english speaker.
discrete-mathematics logic definition relations
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Why is a symmetric relation defined by $forallxforally(xRy implies yRx)$ and not $forallxforally(xRy iff yRx)$?
(I have only found a couple of sources that defines it with a biconditional)
For example, according to Wolfram:
A relation $R$ on a set $S$ is symmetric provided that for every $x$ and $y$ in $S$ we have $xRy iff yRx$.
But the majority of books defines it the other way.
And I think I agree with the second definition.
Because if we use the first definition with "$implies$", we know the truth table of the implication in particular $P implies Q$ is true when $P$ is false and $Q$ is true. That means in the context of symmetric relation that $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And the example $A = 1,2,3,4$ with relation $R = (2,1),(3,1),(4,1)$ satisfies the definition because $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And for me it's weird that this case is considered symmetric.
Or maybe I have a profound confusion with the concept.
I would like that you guys help me clarify. *Sorry for my grammar I'm not a native english speaker.
discrete-mathematics logic definition relations
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
It's for ALL x, y. In your example $(2,1)in R not implies (1,2)in R$. But given $A=1,2,3$ and $R=(1,2),(2,1)$ we have $(1,3)in R implies (3,1)in R$ etc.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:34
1
$begingroup$
"That means in the context of symmetric relation that (x,y)∉ R ⟹ (y,x)∈ R is true" Only if $x,y$ is actually in $R$. $(2,1)not in R implies (1,2)in R$ is a true statement. But $(3,2)not in R implies (2,3)in R$ is a false statement.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:44
2
$begingroup$
The definitions are equivalent.
$endgroup$
– PyRulez
Mar 23 at 18:56
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Why is a symmetric relation defined by $forallxforally(xRy implies yRx)$ and not $forallxforally(xRy iff yRx)$?
(I have only found a couple of sources that defines it with a biconditional)
For example, according to Wolfram:
A relation $R$ on a set $S$ is symmetric provided that for every $x$ and $y$ in $S$ we have $xRy iff yRx$.
But the majority of books defines it the other way.
And I think I agree with the second definition.
Because if we use the first definition with "$implies$", we know the truth table of the implication in particular $P implies Q$ is true when $P$ is false and $Q$ is true. That means in the context of symmetric relation that $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And the example $A = 1,2,3,4$ with relation $R = (2,1),(3,1),(4,1)$ satisfies the definition because $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And for me it's weird that this case is considered symmetric.
Or maybe I have a profound confusion with the concept.
I would like that you guys help me clarify. *Sorry for my grammar I'm not a native english speaker.
discrete-mathematics logic definition relations
$endgroup$
Why is a symmetric relation defined by $forallxforally(xRy implies yRx)$ and not $forallxforally(xRy iff yRx)$?
(I have only found a couple of sources that defines it with a biconditional)
For example, according to Wolfram:
A relation $R$ on a set $S$ is symmetric provided that for every $x$ and $y$ in $S$ we have $xRy iff yRx$.
But the majority of books defines it the other way.
And I think I agree with the second definition.
Because if we use the first definition with "$implies$", we know the truth table of the implication in particular $P implies Q$ is true when $P$ is false and $Q$ is true. That means in the context of symmetric relation that $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And the example $A = 1,2,3,4$ with relation $R = (2,1),(3,1),(4,1)$ satisfies the definition because $(x,y) notin R implies (y,x) in R$ is true.
And for me it's weird that this case is considered symmetric.
Or maybe I have a profound confusion with the concept.
I would like that you guys help me clarify. *Sorry for my grammar I'm not a native english speaker.
discrete-mathematics logic definition relations
discrete-mathematics logic definition relations
edited Mar 23 at 21:44
Asaf Karagila♦
309k33441775
309k33441775
asked Mar 23 at 15:17
Rodrigo SangoRodrigo Sango
1376
1376
$begingroup$
It's for ALL x, y. In your example $(2,1)in R not implies (1,2)in R$. But given $A=1,2,3$ and $R=(1,2),(2,1)$ we have $(1,3)in R implies (3,1)in R$ etc.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:34
1
$begingroup$
"That means in the context of symmetric relation that (x,y)∉ R ⟹ (y,x)∈ R is true" Only if $x,y$ is actually in $R$. $(2,1)not in R implies (1,2)in R$ is a true statement. But $(3,2)not in R implies (2,3)in R$ is a false statement.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:44
2
$begingroup$
The definitions are equivalent.
$endgroup$
– PyRulez
Mar 23 at 18:56
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It's for ALL x, y. In your example $(2,1)in R not implies (1,2)in R$. But given $A=1,2,3$ and $R=(1,2),(2,1)$ we have $(1,3)in R implies (3,1)in R$ etc.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:34
1
$begingroup$
"That means in the context of symmetric relation that (x,y)∉ R ⟹ (y,x)∈ R is true" Only if $x,y$ is actually in $R$. $(2,1)not in R implies (1,2)in R$ is a true statement. But $(3,2)not in R implies (2,3)in R$ is a false statement.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:44
2
$begingroup$
The definitions are equivalent.
$endgroup$
– PyRulez
Mar 23 at 18:56
$begingroup$
It's for ALL x, y. In your example $(2,1)in R not implies (1,2)in R$. But given $A=1,2,3$ and $R=(1,2),(2,1)$ we have $(1,3)in R implies (3,1)in R$ etc.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:34
$begingroup$
It's for ALL x, y. In your example $(2,1)in R not implies (1,2)in R$. But given $A=1,2,3$ and $R=(1,2),(2,1)$ we have $(1,3)in R implies (3,1)in R$ etc.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:34
1
1
$begingroup$
"That means in the context of symmetric relation that (x,y)∉ R ⟹ (y,x)∈ R is true" Only if $x,y$ is actually in $R$. $(2,1)not in R implies (1,2)in R$ is a true statement. But $(3,2)not in R implies (2,3)in R$ is a false statement.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:44
$begingroup$
"That means in the context of symmetric relation that (x,y)∉ R ⟹ (y,x)∈ R is true" Only if $x,y$ is actually in $R$. $(2,1)not in R implies (1,2)in R$ is a true statement. But $(3,2)not in R implies (2,3)in R$ is a false statement.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:44
2
2
$begingroup$
The definitions are equivalent.
$endgroup$
– PyRulez
Mar 23 at 18:56
$begingroup$
The definitions are equivalent.
$endgroup$
– PyRulez
Mar 23 at 18:56
add a comment |
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
For all $x$ and all $y$ make the if and only if unnecessary (albeit perfectly acceptable).
1) $(x,y) in R implies (y,x) in R$ for ALL $x,y in A$
And the statement 2) $(x,y) in R iff (y,x) in R$ are equivalent statements.
If 1) is true and $(x,y) not in R$ then although $(x,y)in Rimplies (y,x)in R$ or $F implies (y,x)in R$ is true, it does not tell us any thing about whether or not $(y,x) in R$. However $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in Y$ tells us that $(y,x) not in R$. Because $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in R$ means $(y,x) in R implies F$. An the only thing that implies a false statement is a false statement. So we must have $(y,x) not in R$.
So in your example you have $(1,2)in Rimplies (2,1)in R$ is true but you don't have $(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$ as true.
So it isn't symmetric.
=====
Another way to look at it:
If $A = 1,2,3$
Then we will have 9 statments.
By 1) the nine statements are:
$(1,1)in Rimplies (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R implies (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R implies (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$
... etc... all nine are needed.
With 2) we also have nine statements:
$(1,1)in Riff (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R iff (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R iff (1,2) in R$
...etc....
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$ and $(2,1) in R iff (1,2)in R$ is redundant.
So aesthetically, using definition 2) is .... inefficient.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
1
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $A$ is a set and $R$ is a binary relation defined on $A$ (that is, $R$ is a subset of $Atimes A$), then the usual definition of symmetry (as far as $R$ is concerned) is$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryimplies ymathrel Rx.tag1$$And this is equivalent to$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryiff ymathrel Rx.tag2$$So, why do we choose $(1)$ instead of $(2)$ in general? Because, in general (although not in this case) it is easier to verify the assertion $Aimplies B$ than $Aiff B$. And (again, in general), when we choose between two distinct but equivalent definitions, we usually choose the one which is easier to verify that it holds.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $xRy implies yRx$ for all $x$ and all $y$, then we can choose $x := tildey$ and $y := tildex$ and get $tildeyRtildex implies tildexRtildey$ or, equivalently, $yRx implies xRy$, which is $impliedby$.
In conclusion, since the implication should hold for all $x,y$, the equivalence already holds.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let it be that $R$ is a symmetric relation.
This according to the first mentioned definition:$$forall xforall y[xRyimplies yRx]tag1$$
Now let it be that $aRb$.
Then we are allowed to conclude that $bRa$.
On the other hand if $bRa$ then also we are conclude that $aRb$.
So apparantly we have:$$aRbiff bRa$$
Proved is now that for a symmetric relation $R$ (based on definition $(1)$) we have:$$forall xforall y[xRyiff yRx]tag2$$
So $(2)$ is a necessary condition for $(1)$.
Next to that it is obvious that $(2)$ is also a sufficient condition for $(1)$ so actually the statements are equivalent.
Both can be used as definition then, but in cases like that it is good custom to go for the one with less implications. This for instance decreases the chance on redundant work if we try to prove that a relation is indeed symmetric.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);
else
createEditor();
);
function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);
);
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3159427%2fwhy-is-a-symmetric-relation-defined-forall-x-forall-y-xry-implies-yrx-and%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
4 Answers
4
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
For all $x$ and all $y$ make the if and only if unnecessary (albeit perfectly acceptable).
1) $(x,y) in R implies (y,x) in R$ for ALL $x,y in A$
And the statement 2) $(x,y) in R iff (y,x) in R$ are equivalent statements.
If 1) is true and $(x,y) not in R$ then although $(x,y)in Rimplies (y,x)in R$ or $F implies (y,x)in R$ is true, it does not tell us any thing about whether or not $(y,x) in R$. However $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in Y$ tells us that $(y,x) not in R$. Because $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in R$ means $(y,x) in R implies F$. An the only thing that implies a false statement is a false statement. So we must have $(y,x) not in R$.
So in your example you have $(1,2)in Rimplies (2,1)in R$ is true but you don't have $(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$ as true.
So it isn't symmetric.
=====
Another way to look at it:
If $A = 1,2,3$
Then we will have 9 statments.
By 1) the nine statements are:
$(1,1)in Rimplies (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R implies (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R implies (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$
... etc... all nine are needed.
With 2) we also have nine statements:
$(1,1)in Riff (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R iff (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R iff (1,2) in R$
...etc....
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$ and $(2,1) in R iff (1,2)in R$ is redundant.
So aesthetically, using definition 2) is .... inefficient.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
1
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
add a comment |
$begingroup$
For all $x$ and all $y$ make the if and only if unnecessary (albeit perfectly acceptable).
1) $(x,y) in R implies (y,x) in R$ for ALL $x,y in A$
And the statement 2) $(x,y) in R iff (y,x) in R$ are equivalent statements.
If 1) is true and $(x,y) not in R$ then although $(x,y)in Rimplies (y,x)in R$ or $F implies (y,x)in R$ is true, it does not tell us any thing about whether or not $(y,x) in R$. However $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in Y$ tells us that $(y,x) not in R$. Because $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in R$ means $(y,x) in R implies F$. An the only thing that implies a false statement is a false statement. So we must have $(y,x) not in R$.
So in your example you have $(1,2)in Rimplies (2,1)in R$ is true but you don't have $(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$ as true.
So it isn't symmetric.
=====
Another way to look at it:
If $A = 1,2,3$
Then we will have 9 statments.
By 1) the nine statements are:
$(1,1)in Rimplies (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R implies (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R implies (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$
... etc... all nine are needed.
With 2) we also have nine statements:
$(1,1)in Riff (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R iff (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R iff (1,2) in R$
...etc....
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$ and $(2,1) in R iff (1,2)in R$ is redundant.
So aesthetically, using definition 2) is .... inefficient.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
1
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
add a comment |
$begingroup$
For all $x$ and all $y$ make the if and only if unnecessary (albeit perfectly acceptable).
1) $(x,y) in R implies (y,x) in R$ for ALL $x,y in A$
And the statement 2) $(x,y) in R iff (y,x) in R$ are equivalent statements.
If 1) is true and $(x,y) not in R$ then although $(x,y)in Rimplies (y,x)in R$ or $F implies (y,x)in R$ is true, it does not tell us any thing about whether or not $(y,x) in R$. However $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in Y$ tells us that $(y,x) not in R$. Because $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in R$ means $(y,x) in R implies F$. An the only thing that implies a false statement is a false statement. So we must have $(y,x) not in R$.
So in your example you have $(1,2)in Rimplies (2,1)in R$ is true but you don't have $(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$ as true.
So it isn't symmetric.
=====
Another way to look at it:
If $A = 1,2,3$
Then we will have 9 statments.
By 1) the nine statements are:
$(1,1)in Rimplies (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R implies (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R implies (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$
... etc... all nine are needed.
With 2) we also have nine statements:
$(1,1)in Riff (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R iff (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R iff (1,2) in R$
...etc....
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$ and $(2,1) in R iff (1,2)in R$ is redundant.
So aesthetically, using definition 2) is .... inefficient.
$endgroup$
For all $x$ and all $y$ make the if and only if unnecessary (albeit perfectly acceptable).
1) $(x,y) in R implies (y,x) in R$ for ALL $x,y in A$
And the statement 2) $(x,y) in R iff (y,x) in R$ are equivalent statements.
If 1) is true and $(x,y) not in R$ then although $(x,y)in Rimplies (y,x)in R$ or $F implies (y,x)in R$ is true, it does not tell us any thing about whether or not $(y,x) in R$. However $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in Y$ tells us that $(y,x) not in R$. Because $(y,x) in R implies (x,y) in R$ means $(y,x) in R implies F$. An the only thing that implies a false statement is a false statement. So we must have $(y,x) not in R$.
So in your example you have $(1,2)in Rimplies (2,1)in R$ is true but you don't have $(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$ as true.
So it isn't symmetric.
=====
Another way to look at it:
If $A = 1,2,3$
Then we will have 9 statments.
By 1) the nine statements are:
$(1,1)in Rimplies (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R implies (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R implies (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R implies (1,2) in R$
... etc... all nine are needed.
With 2) we also have nine statements:
$(1,1)in Riff (1,1) in R$
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$
$(1,3) in R iff (3,1) in R$
$(2,1) in R iff (1,2) in R$
...etc....
$(1,2) in R iff (2,1) in R$ and $(2,1) in R iff (1,2)in R$ is redundant.
So aesthetically, using definition 2) is .... inefficient.
answered Mar 23 at 16:09
fleabloodfleablood
1
1
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
1
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
1
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
$begingroup$
Got it. Thank you, fleablood.
$endgroup$
– Rodrigo Sango
Mar 23 at 16:16
1
1
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
"all nine are needed" ... except the three that are tautologies, of course. But it would be more work and less clear to exclude them than to tolerate them.
$endgroup$
– Henning Makholm
Mar 23 at 18:57
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
$begingroup$
Well, none of them are needed if you state it as all $(x,y)$ but that includes, for each $(x,y)$, $(y,x)$ as well so... well, why say more than you need to.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 24 at 2:14
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $A$ is a set and $R$ is a binary relation defined on $A$ (that is, $R$ is a subset of $Atimes A$), then the usual definition of symmetry (as far as $R$ is concerned) is$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryimplies ymathrel Rx.tag1$$And this is equivalent to$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryiff ymathrel Rx.tag2$$So, why do we choose $(1)$ instead of $(2)$ in general? Because, in general (although not in this case) it is easier to verify the assertion $Aimplies B$ than $Aiff B$. And (again, in general), when we choose between two distinct but equivalent definitions, we usually choose the one which is easier to verify that it holds.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $A$ is a set and $R$ is a binary relation defined on $A$ (that is, $R$ is a subset of $Atimes A$), then the usual definition of symmetry (as far as $R$ is concerned) is$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryimplies ymathrel Rx.tag1$$And this is equivalent to$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryiff ymathrel Rx.tag2$$So, why do we choose $(1)$ instead of $(2)$ in general? Because, in general (although not in this case) it is easier to verify the assertion $Aimplies B$ than $Aiff B$. And (again, in general), when we choose between two distinct but equivalent definitions, we usually choose the one which is easier to verify that it holds.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $A$ is a set and $R$ is a binary relation defined on $A$ (that is, $R$ is a subset of $Atimes A$), then the usual definition of symmetry (as far as $R$ is concerned) is$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryimplies ymathrel Rx.tag1$$And this is equivalent to$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryiff ymathrel Rx.tag2$$So, why do we choose $(1)$ instead of $(2)$ in general? Because, in general (although not in this case) it is easier to verify the assertion $Aimplies B$ than $Aiff B$. And (again, in general), when we choose between two distinct but equivalent definitions, we usually choose the one which is easier to verify that it holds.
$endgroup$
If $A$ is a set and $R$ is a binary relation defined on $A$ (that is, $R$ is a subset of $Atimes A$), then the usual definition of symmetry (as far as $R$ is concerned) is$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryimplies ymathrel Rx.tag1$$And this is equivalent to$$(forall xin A)(forall yin A):xmathrel Ryiff ymathrel Rx.tag2$$So, why do we choose $(1)$ instead of $(2)$ in general? Because, in general (although not in this case) it is easier to verify the assertion $Aimplies B$ than $Aiff B$. And (again, in general), when we choose between two distinct but equivalent definitions, we usually choose the one which is easier to verify that it holds.
answered Mar 23 at 15:25
José Carlos SantosJosé Carlos Santos
176k24137246
176k24137246
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $xRy implies yRx$ for all $x$ and all $y$, then we can choose $x := tildey$ and $y := tildex$ and get $tildeyRtildex implies tildexRtildey$ or, equivalently, $yRx implies xRy$, which is $impliedby$.
In conclusion, since the implication should hold for all $x,y$, the equivalence already holds.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $xRy implies yRx$ for all $x$ and all $y$, then we can choose $x := tildey$ and $y := tildex$ and get $tildeyRtildex implies tildexRtildey$ or, equivalently, $yRx implies xRy$, which is $impliedby$.
In conclusion, since the implication should hold for all $x,y$, the equivalence already holds.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
If $xRy implies yRx$ for all $x$ and all $y$, then we can choose $x := tildey$ and $y := tildex$ and get $tildeyRtildex implies tildexRtildey$ or, equivalently, $yRx implies xRy$, which is $impliedby$.
In conclusion, since the implication should hold for all $x,y$, the equivalence already holds.
$endgroup$
If $xRy implies yRx$ for all $x$ and all $y$, then we can choose $x := tildey$ and $y := tildex$ and get $tildeyRtildex implies tildexRtildey$ or, equivalently, $yRx implies xRy$, which is $impliedby$.
In conclusion, since the implication should hold for all $x,y$, the equivalence already holds.
answered Mar 23 at 15:21
Viktor GlombikViktor Glombik
1,3572628
1,3572628
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let it be that $R$ is a symmetric relation.
This according to the first mentioned definition:$$forall xforall y[xRyimplies yRx]tag1$$
Now let it be that $aRb$.
Then we are allowed to conclude that $bRa$.
On the other hand if $bRa$ then also we are conclude that $aRb$.
So apparantly we have:$$aRbiff bRa$$
Proved is now that for a symmetric relation $R$ (based on definition $(1)$) we have:$$forall xforall y[xRyiff yRx]tag2$$
So $(2)$ is a necessary condition for $(1)$.
Next to that it is obvious that $(2)$ is also a sufficient condition for $(1)$ so actually the statements are equivalent.
Both can be used as definition then, but in cases like that it is good custom to go for the one with less implications. This for instance decreases the chance on redundant work if we try to prove that a relation is indeed symmetric.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let it be that $R$ is a symmetric relation.
This according to the first mentioned definition:$$forall xforall y[xRyimplies yRx]tag1$$
Now let it be that $aRb$.
Then we are allowed to conclude that $bRa$.
On the other hand if $bRa$ then also we are conclude that $aRb$.
So apparantly we have:$$aRbiff bRa$$
Proved is now that for a symmetric relation $R$ (based on definition $(1)$) we have:$$forall xforall y[xRyiff yRx]tag2$$
So $(2)$ is a necessary condition for $(1)$.
Next to that it is obvious that $(2)$ is also a sufficient condition for $(1)$ so actually the statements are equivalent.
Both can be used as definition then, but in cases like that it is good custom to go for the one with less implications. This for instance decreases the chance on redundant work if we try to prove that a relation is indeed symmetric.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let it be that $R$ is a symmetric relation.
This according to the first mentioned definition:$$forall xforall y[xRyimplies yRx]tag1$$
Now let it be that $aRb$.
Then we are allowed to conclude that $bRa$.
On the other hand if $bRa$ then also we are conclude that $aRb$.
So apparantly we have:$$aRbiff bRa$$
Proved is now that for a symmetric relation $R$ (based on definition $(1)$) we have:$$forall xforall y[xRyiff yRx]tag2$$
So $(2)$ is a necessary condition for $(1)$.
Next to that it is obvious that $(2)$ is also a sufficient condition for $(1)$ so actually the statements are equivalent.
Both can be used as definition then, but in cases like that it is good custom to go for the one with less implications. This for instance decreases the chance on redundant work if we try to prove that a relation is indeed symmetric.
$endgroup$
Let it be that $R$ is a symmetric relation.
This according to the first mentioned definition:$$forall xforall y[xRyimplies yRx]tag1$$
Now let it be that $aRb$.
Then we are allowed to conclude that $bRa$.
On the other hand if $bRa$ then also we are conclude that $aRb$.
So apparantly we have:$$aRbiff bRa$$
Proved is now that for a symmetric relation $R$ (based on definition $(1)$) we have:$$forall xforall y[xRyiff yRx]tag2$$
So $(2)$ is a necessary condition for $(1)$.
Next to that it is obvious that $(2)$ is also a sufficient condition for $(1)$ so actually the statements are equivalent.
Both can be used as definition then, but in cases like that it is good custom to go for the one with less implications. This for instance decreases the chance on redundant work if we try to prove that a relation is indeed symmetric.
edited Mar 26 at 9:13
answered Mar 23 at 15:30
drhabdrhab
104k545136
104k545136
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3159427%2fwhy-is-a-symmetric-relation-defined-forall-x-forall-y-xry-implies-yrx-and%23new-answer', 'question_page');
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function ()
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
);
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
$begingroup$
It's for ALL x, y. In your example $(2,1)in R not implies (1,2)in R$. But given $A=1,2,3$ and $R=(1,2),(2,1)$ we have $(1,3)in R implies (3,1)in R$ etc.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:34
1
$begingroup$
"That means in the context of symmetric relation that (x,y)∉ R ⟹ (y,x)∈ R is true" Only if $x,y$ is actually in $R$. $(2,1)not in R implies (1,2)in R$ is a true statement. But $(3,2)not in R implies (2,3)in R$ is a false statement.
$endgroup$
– fleablood
Mar 23 at 15:44
2
$begingroup$
The definitions are equivalent.
$endgroup$
– PyRulez
Mar 23 at 18:56